Saint Thomas Aquinas Term Paper

PAGES
15
WORDS
4950
Cite

Saint Thomas Aquinas Thomas Aquinas lived and died between 1225-74. He was an Italian philosopher and theologian. He was the Doctor of the Church, also acknowledged as the Angelic Doctor. He is the supreme stature of scholasticism, one of the most important saints of the Roman Catholic Church, as well as, originator of the system acknowledged by Pope Leo XIII to be the legitimate Catholic philosophy (1).

This article argues that Thomas Aquinas's political philosophy is un-egalitarian. Not only does Aquinas disappoints to give his support to an egalitarian outlook of political impartiality, but so as to explain his political philosophy properly one has got to ascribe to him an idea intensely undemocratic in its repercussions. This paper proposes, consequently, that by means of Aquinas's thought, as a rational foundation for democracy would need a considerable reconsideration of his own point-of-view.

The purpose of this paper is neither to call into question the attractiveness of liberal democratic policy nor to revitalize Aquinas's political point-of-views. Understanding Aquinas's political philosophy properly assists us to understand some of the background against which contemporary political philosophy, together with modern Thomisms, materialized. It assists us to distinguish where interpretations have been done in Aquinas's philosophy. This drops light on what it is for Thomism to be a living institution and highlights the innovation of those philosophers who have made the interpretations.

Review of Related Literature

The Concept of Democratic and Undemocratic Political Philosophy

By asserting Aquinas's political thought undemocratic, it does not mean merely that he did not encourage measures for political management customarily associated with the expression "democracy." Instead this paper presents thoughts, suppositions, as well as, point-of-views fundamental to his political philosophy, ones that could be utilized to demonstrate the preferability of one structure of management making over another. To resolve the question whether Aquinas was a democratic or a proto-democratic philosopher, it is not sufficient to indicate that he articulated a fondness for anarchy or for a "combined government" elsewhere. Nor can the question be established by going further than constitutional themes to Aquinas's assertion that human beings are evenly made in God's reflection and portrait. Although democrats are dedicated to political fairness, human impartiality does not involve political impartiality; there are democratic, as well as, undemocratic comprehensions of political impartiality. Aquinas would have to demonstrate that the philosophy of human impartiality understood in his assertion that, all are made in God's reflection, is political and democratic rather than not (1).

What would respond to the question of whether a particular group of political philosophy is democratic is challenging to pinpoint specifically. As an initial estimation, it is assumed that an obligation to democracy involves an obligation to the observation that fundamental dissimilarities amongst people are politically inappropriate. This estimation requires substantial alteration so as to observe its repercussions for Aquinas's viewpoints. Consider what is called "political relationship." Any normative political assumption has got to say something on the subject of the rudiments of which political society is organized. The apparentness of the maxim that political societies are organizations of human beings can blind us to an imperative reality. Any formation of those human rudiments competent of supporting normative conclusions has got to be spelled out hypothetically. "Political relationship" assumes the genuine or possible capability for benefiting from ends, and for working out the powers of practical rationale. Theories change considerably in how they identify principles for "political relationship" in a high-performing political society, in the powers, welfares, as well as, capacities that "political relationship" assumes, and in relation to what standing "political relationship" essentially presents (4).

How dissimilar accounts of "political relationship" are identified will rely upon what diverse theorists presume to be the most important aspects of the societies they deal with. Characteristically democratic philosophies continue from the hypothesis that the sharing of opportunities, liberties, as well as, capital is mainly controlled by their society's leading machinery, one that is capable to support its power by a domination on vindicated compulsion. The distributive function of government and its coercive nature are consequently the aspects of society that encourage democratic hypotheses in the first place. To have a "political relationship" with the society, consistent with these hypotheses, is to have access to opportunities, liberties, as well as, capital, and to work out some control over the central machinery that manages their circulation. More specifically, consistent with these hypotheses, associates of society are citizens. They are co-owners of...

...

At the same time control of this position assumes that the personnel who have it possess the abilities they require, they are supposed to have their rank in spite of dissimilarities in the quantity to which they possess the abilities that citizenship needs. Democratic hypotheses are dedicated to the unrestricted outlook of "political relationship (4)."
This paper is not presenting this observation as a classification of democracy. Instead this paper is asserting that it articulates an indispensable constituent of conventional democratic viewpoints of political fairness. For the reason that democratic hypotheses support it, they are dedicated to sharing of political authority that is asserted as "democratic." One cannot preserve this proposition comprehensively, but observes that it fits predominantly well with the contractualist custom of democratic hypothesis from its genesis in Locke to the current composition of Rawls, a custom that has emphasized the fairness, frequently the natural impartiality, of human beings. Conventional advocates of this outlook, for example Locke, vivified their obligation to impartiality by appealing to a state of nature in which natural human capacities were on exhibit. Consequently in Locke's state of nature, managers are portrayed as equals in their aptitude to rationale; they are presumed to have welfares in protecting their lives, liberties, as well as, estates. In Rawl's original pose, parties are correspondingly equivalent and unaware of dissimilarities in their interests. Locke and Rawls presume that associates of society are equivalent. They take this to have significant implications for delivering political authority, rights, as well as, liberties, and in Rawl's situation, wealth, income, as well as, opportunities. The surroundings of the state of nature and the initial position allow Locke and Rawls to symbolize the elementary impartiality of citizens and to prolong the political repercussions that place their hypotheses in the democratic custom (4).

By distinction, in Aquinas's outlook, associates of society are co-members in its common good. Aquinas thought that involvement in a society's common good needs ownership of the well being and perhaps unrecognized abilities involved by a personified intellectual nature. However, Aquinas does not presume that dissimilarities in these endowments or in the customs they are recognized are immaterial to association in political society or to its recognition of the common good. Quite the opposite, he supposes that there are significant dissimilarities even amongst common adult associates of political culture. He makes a case that recognizing the common good relies upon balancing these dissimilarities so that each recompenses for what others require, and dissimilarities effort for the good of all. He believes that in a high-performing political society, associates perfect or supplement one another. Aquinas consequently supports what might be described the supplementarity outlook of political relationship (6).

Aquinas's thought that associates of a high-performing political society supplement one another has philosophical repercussions for how he cared for power and distributive impartiality. He did not stretch these repercussions by asking about the circumstances of humankind in a quasi-Lockean state of nature. Believing human beings are in nature social and political, Aquinas would dispute that a state in which they were unchanged by political organizations would not be their natural one. He was not involved in the query of what human beings would be like under such conditions. He is, on the other hand, strongly involved in the state of humans devoid of the effect of sins. Aquinas consequently conversed the state of innocence in some detail. Although he maintained that the state of innocence was not a state of "pure nature" for the reason of the stirring influences of elegance, he discusses the state of innocence as one in which certain natural human situation and trends would have been present. Amongst these are natural differences and supplementarity amongst human beings. In conversing the state of innocence, Aquinas also drew out the political repercussions of these circumstances. It is indispensable not to blunder the state of innocence for a state of nature or to presume that the states of innocence and nature are presented to respond the similar questions. Still, examining Aquinas's behavior of the former brings to light the political costs of his supplementarity outlook, just as examining Locke's conduct of the latter clarifies the political costs of his democratic one (6).

Having expressed an approximate concept of what is meant by the supplementarity observation of political relationship, this paper will now demonstrate that Aquinas possesses this vision of relationship and that it is fundamental to his social and political philosophy. In view of the fact that Aquinas held the supplementarity observation instead of the egalitarian observation on the subject of political relationship, he did not hold a…

Sources Used in Documents:

Bibliography

1). Allen Buchanan. Justice as Reciprocity vs. Subject-Centered Justice. Philosophy and Public Affairs 119 (1990) 227-52.

2). Aidan Nichols. Discovering Aquinas: An Introduction to His Life, Work, and Influence. (W.W. Norton & Company; 1987)

3). Brian Davies. The Thought of Thomas Aquinas. (Clarendon Press, 1993)

4). John Finnis. Natural Law and Natural Right. (New York: Oxford University, 1981)


Cite this Document:

"Saint Thomas Aquinas" (2004, April 18) Retrieved April 25, 2024, from
https://www.paperdue.com/essay/saint-thomas-aquinas-168777

"Saint Thomas Aquinas" 18 April 2004. Web.25 April. 2024. <
https://www.paperdue.com/essay/saint-thomas-aquinas-168777>

"Saint Thomas Aquinas", 18 April 2004, Accessed.25 April. 2024,
https://www.paperdue.com/essay/saint-thomas-aquinas-168777

Related Documents

Therefore the Old Law should have been given to all nations, and not to one people only. (Aquinas: 811) Aquinas responds in these words: Although the salvation, which was to come through Christ, was prepared for all nations, yet it was necessary that Christ should be born of one people, which, for this reason, was privileged above other peoples, according to Rom. ix. 4: To whom, namely, the Jews, belongeth the

" To that, Aquinas responded that the perfect beatitude, in Bradley's paraphrase, "...through grace, has a sort of beginning in this life," and while on earth humans need friends to achieve the material and spiritual input that keeps them seeking happiness, "In heaven," Bradley paraphrases, "the society of friends is not an essential or necessary condition for enjoying the vision of God, Who as the perfect good, in and of

St. Thomas Aquinas
PAGES 2 WORDS 942

Saint Thomas Aquinas was a thirteenth century Dominican monk: Soccio notes that "Dominicans were dedicated to education and to preaching to common people" (Soccio 219). It is this learned quality which permeates Aquinas' approach to building a Christian system of philosophy: Aquinas is usually considered part of a larger medieval intellectual movement known as Scholasticism. Scholasticism represented an attempt on the part of Christian thinkers of the middle ages to

The nobility worked together with the urban citizens in order to limit the powers of the royalty. The Crown, on the other hand, joined the municipal/city governments to weaken the forces of the feudal (Minlan, 2007). The principles of the feudal society also maintained that the King depends on himself for a living but if the King is in need of what can be called as some sort of non-feudal

Thomas Aquinas is the most important figure of his age. Many people have heard of Thomas Aquinas, but fewer know why he is the most important figure of the 1200s and beyond. Thomas Aquinas was a Dominican monk, a writer, and a philosopher. He created much of the modern Catholic Church doctrine and regulations, and was made a saint in 1323. Thomas combined the best of theologian and philosopher, and

160). Furthermore, Aquinas considers all people as being creations of God and parts of a whole that God represents. God's perfection has been passed on to its creations and thus all humans are perfect in their nature. Aquinas is obsessed with demonstrating the existence of God and this can be seen in most of his writings. F.C. Copleston elucidates the reason for this through the fact that "in arguing for