Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Is One Term Paper

PAGES
5
WORDS
2143
Cite

These [bad effects of pleasure and pain] are the reason why people actually define the virtues as ways of being unaffected and undisturbed [by pleasures and pains]" (1104b21-25) It is not imperative to remain indifferent or unaffected by both pleasure and pain to be virtuous, it is only essential that we have the right feelings of pleasure and pain at the right time. Therefore, he goes on defining virtue as the right state in front of pleasure and pain:

We assume, then, that virtue is the sort of state that does the best actions concerning pleasures and pains, and that vice is the contrary state."(1104b26-27)

Thus, Aristotle sums up his discussion and concludes that virtue is all about the feelings of pleasure and pain, and that the actions, even if they are good can decrease virtue when they are done badly:

To sum up: Virtue is about pleasures and pains; the actions that are its sources also increase it or, if they are done badly, ruin it; and its activity is about the same actions as those that are its sources."(1105a15-16)

Hursthouse also summarizes Aristotle's theory about virtue in the same way, asserting that the appropriate feelings are actually what define an action as virtuous:

And, according to virtue ethics, the agent with the inappropriate feelings does not act virtuously, in the very way or manner that the virtuous agent acts."(Hursthouse, 125)

The theory Aristotle proposes of virtue is continued by his definition of the human soul and its 'contents'. He argues that the virtue is a state of soul and of the individual,...

...

The virtue of eyes, for instance, makes the eyes and their functioning excellent, because it makes us see well; and similarly, the virtue of a horse makes the horse excellent, and thereby good at galloping, at carrying its rider, and at standing steady in the face of the enemy. If this is true in every case, the virtue of a human being will likewise be the state that makes a human being good and makes him perform his function well. (1105b30-1106a)
His comparison of the virtuous character of a man with the 'virtue' of the eyes that make one see well indicates that he considers virtue as the state of soul that determines the proper 'functioning' of the individual, that is, that which makes him perform the best actions.

In this way, we see that for Aristotle the optimal actions of a certain human being are the result of the virtuous character, which is in fact, a state of the soul. The virtuous character is in its turn, determined by the other states, or the feelings of pleasure and pain experienced in a certain situation or when performing a particular action. His implication is that no action is good of itself, unless supported by the proper feelings, and that this would be the essence of ethics.

Works Cited

Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1985

Hursthouse, Rosalind. On Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999

Sources Used in Documents:

Works Cited

Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1985

Hursthouse, Rosalind. On Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999


Cite this Document:

"Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Is One" (2007, February 25) Retrieved April 25, 2024, from
https://www.paperdue.com/essay/aristotle-nicomachean-ethics-is-one-39807

"Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Is One" 25 February 2007. Web.25 April. 2024. <
https://www.paperdue.com/essay/aristotle-nicomachean-ethics-is-one-39807>

"Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Is One", 25 February 2007, Accessed.25 April. 2024,
https://www.paperdue.com/essay/aristotle-nicomachean-ethics-is-one-39807

Related Documents

Unlike either deontological or utilitarian ethics, virtue ethics focuses on character. Because virtue ethics are not consequentialist, overall virtue ethical frameworks are more akin to deontological analysis of moral right and wrong. One’s intentions are as important as one’s actions; the consequences of one’s actions are important but not as much as remaining honest, compassionate, and willing to learn. At the same time, Aristotle and other proponents of virtue ethics

Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle said, "The good for man is an activity of the soul in accordance with virtue, or if there are more kinds of virtue than one, in accordance with the best and most perfect kind" (). According to Aristotle and his Nicomachean ethics, there are two kinds of virtue: intellectual and moral. Intellectual virtues are learned by instruction and moral virtues are learned by practice. According to his theory,

Acting in accordance with virtuous principles is a key to attaining happiness. In Book Three of the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle explains the difference between voluntary and involuntary action as well as total passivity. In the first chapter of the book, the philosopher explains the importance of free will and taking action in determining ethical behavior. Aristotle concludes that the only truly ethical acts are those that are chosen by

If this was the case, and this transformation of reasoning did occur, then that person would be truly virtuous. There are many strengths to Aristotle's argument, as well. One of the main strengths is the discussion of the two kinds of virtue - the kind that comes from habit, and the kind that comes from learning. This would work to demonstrate why some people change so much as they grow

Aristotle thought happiness was longer in coming, it was the manner of being actualized and fulfilling one's true potential using their own individual gifts: Again, if the virtues are concerned with actions and passions, and every passion and every action is accompanied by pleasure and pain, for this reason also virtue will be concerned with pleasures and pains. This is indicated also by the fact that punishment is indicated by

perceive as Aristotle's best work known work on ethics, Nichomachean Ethics, sheds light on what Aristotle believed was happiness. "…happiness would seem to need this sort of prosperity added also; that is why some people identify happiness with good fortune, while others < eacting from one extreme to the other> identify it with virtue" (Aristotle, Irwin, & Fine, p. 360). His perception of what is happiness implies: that it itself is